Two things struck me as questionable: the appeal to mathematics and the assumption of utilitarianism. Complicated equations are periodically brought in to illustrate or explain certain points, in a way that struck me as unnecessary. I think it's at least excusable, though, if students are to learn to evaluate Duflo's and Banerjee's work for themselves or to carry out such work independently in future. In other words, it was not necessary in this course but as preparation for related work afterwards it might be useful. I don't know.
The maths felt a bit like a display of rigor, a way to show that what was being done was at least related to academic seriousness and intellectual difficulty. It made me think about rigor-accessories in other subjects. In philosophy, for instance, you might have to pass exams in formal logic and a foreign language to get a PhD. And some papers bring in formal logic in seemingly needless ways to demonstrate rigor. I'm suspicious of this kind of thing, but I can't say it's always a waste of time.
I was reminded of all that when I read this rejection of economics. I don't agree that economics should just be scrapped, but there is something to this:
Mathematical, formal, and technical language certainly can be useful, but they can so easily be reached for as something to hide behind that it's often worth being suspicious and, where possible, ignoring them to focus on what is actually being said rather than the impressively learned way it is being presented. In ordinary language philosophy there is no such hiding, which is a good thing.Biology uses maths when it needs it, but gets on very well as a perfectly rigorous scientific discipline most of the time without it. In spite of the prejudice of some scientists towards the mathematical, nobody feels that biology needs more equations to be taken seriously.But there is one academic discipline that does seem to feel the need to dress up its ideas in mathematical language. Economists have always dabbled in numbers, and have become more and more enamoured of them as the years go by. Economics as taught at university level is now full of differential equations and the like.
Possibly more problematic for Duflo and Banerjee is their consequentialism, which is mostly under the surface and not explicitly recognized or defended even when it comes into plain view. The main example I can think of concerns microcredit organizations. Muhammad Yunus argues (or at least asserts) that:
credit programs that seek to profit from the suffering of the poor should not be described as “microcredit,” and investors who own such programs should not be allowed to benefit from the trust and respect that microcredit banks have rightly earned.He is concerned, in part, with the mission of microcredit banks, which he thinks should be to relieve suffering caused by poverty rather than to make a profit. Banerjee and Duflo counter that profitable banks do relieve the suffering of the poor. They are probably right, but they are ignoring the moral aspect of Yunus' complaint. He says:
Commercialization has been a terrible wrong turn for microfinance, and it indicates a worrying “mission drift” in the motivation of those lending to the poor. Poverty should be eradicated, not seen as a money-making opportunity.It's true that he goes on to talk about the kind of practical problems that would concern a consequentialist, but he seems also to care about motivation, not just consequences. There is something obscene, one might think, about seeing poverty as a money-making opportunity. This kind of concern, whether ultimately reasonable or not, is simply ignored by Duflo and Banerjee. Nor do they say that this is a philosophical question and that students who are interested in it should take a relevant ethics course. They just ignore it, as if it did not exist.
This kind of philosophy blindness seems to be common. My local city council is currently considering whether to continue giving money to organizations that provide various more or less charitable services. One member of the council has reportedly said that he wishes he could support them but that it simply isn't the function of government to do so. This is to treat a philosophical or ideological position as if it were something like a physical law. A friend of mine who heard about the problem suggested that the council needs more facts, and denied that there are questions of value that could not be solved by the gathering of more facts. Having just typed this I think I must have misunderstood what he was saying, but he seemed to want to deny the fact/value distinction so entirely that he ended up talking about ideas concerning the proper function of government as if they could be evaluated purely by looking at data. I have also known people talk as if moral relativism is just undeniably true and others to take utilitarianism to be so obviously right that they didn't even recognize that it is a debatable position. In short, a lot of educated people seem to be unable to identify philosophical issues. It's a sort of blindness to the existence of questions, of various logical spaces, of the possibility of thinking differently.
I think that if everyone's education included consideration of, for instance, the fact/value distinction and some basic ethical theory then the problem would be reduced (though not eradicated). Someone might then remind people suffering from temporary blindness of their high school or college philosophy course. But how many introductory-level philosophy courses spend much time on the fact/value distinction? Mine don't. And the problem might not be so much the ability to see these questions but the willingness to look. A lot of what looks like stupidity is a failure to think about causal connections. This kind of thing: if I leave the gate open and then open the door the dog might run out, which will be bad. Or: if I move into that lane now then the car nearest me will have to slow down suddenly, which could cause an accident, which will be bad. It's not that people can't think that far ahead but too often they don't bother to do so. Partly, I think, because the "which will be bad" part is erased by a giant WHATEVER.
That, I suppose, is because we are imperfect creatures. And because we are so occupied by other things. And we don't get enough sleep. But also because we don't have as much of a sense of the reality of other people as we should. Our attitude towards them is not an attitude towards a soul but more like the attitude we have towards a minor character in a movie. They look human but their fate is no concern of ours. This is partly because there are so many people around that it is hard to care much about all of them. Perhaps it is also because we watch so much TV, play so many computer games, and spend so much time online. And when we do these things we are inside, interacting with no one, practicing passivity. That might not change our thinking or our behavior, but it is in line with our tendency not to think of ourselves as having any kind of role to play in society, any kind of job to do other than one that pays us money. I saw someone recently telling people in the UK that it is their duty to vote in the upcoming election. The very idea of duty seems extremely old-fashioned. Who now believes that we have any such thing? Of those who do, how many care much about it?
There clearly are people who have a strong sense of community and of something that might be called duty, whether they would use that word or not. But the number of such people seems to be going down. Margaret Thatcher's claim that there is no such thing as society was shocking at the time. It now seems commonplace. So far as that kind of individualism goes hand in hand with a certain kind of economics, it is good to see economists like Banerjee and Duflo doing something else.
i like the idea of philosophy blindness. i like the term. as a term of criticism it seems to me accurate. and i like the fact that you are using it in the context of a discussion of economics. it seems to me that social scientists (also psychologists) are more likely to be guilty of that. Or perhaps they just have their own way of being so?
ReplyDeletei'd like to ask you many questions about this: whether philosophers are ever guilty of that; whether one could be guilty of the opposite failure--seeing too much philosophy, even when it is not there; whether there are different kinds of this blindness--for social scientists, for artists, for mathematicians; whether it is a failure of the understanding or of the imagination; whether there are other philosophical problems people tend to be blind to, beside those connected with the assuming the truth of utilitarianism and moral relativism; with what other moral and intellectual failings would it be useful to compare this failing--soul blindness, empiricism, the wish that if you ignore a problem it will disappear...
i'm not expecting full answers to any of these questions. it just seems to me a notion worth developing.
Thanks, Reshef.
DeleteI'm sure that philosophers are guilty of philosophy blindness too. Some of this might be a matter of turning a blind eye to questions the philosopher does not want to address, but some of it is simply a matter of not seeing an issue (either not seeing it at all or not seeing it as worth bothering with, seeing it only dimly). Perhaps I'm too confident in making these assertions, but when I read work by non-Wittgensteinian philosophers it often seems blind to questions that he raises and that seem relevant to me. Probably philosophers are less likely to be completely philosophy blind than others, but it's not as if we all see philosophical issues perfectly all the time. I'm sure I don't (and by seeing them I just mean seeing that they are there, not seeing them perfectly clearly).
To get anywhere you have to not stop and philosophize all the time, so turning a blind eye to questions one could ask is probably necessary sometimes. But to do so consciously is not the same as going ahead unaware that anything has been overlooked.
Could you see too much philosophy? If seeing it gets in the way then I suppose that is seeing too much, but (I would think) you could always see it but choose not to get involved. If you need to do your taxes (and so are doing some mathematics) then you probably shouldn't start asking questions about the philosophy of mathematics until you have finished doing them.
Aside from this kind of practical problem I can imagine someone thinking there was a philosophical issue when there really wasn't one. This would involve asking too many questions. I'm thinking of someone trying too hard with a theory they like, imagining linguistic problems where there really aren't any, or political problems, perhaps. I'm not sure how we would sort out which problems are real and which not though.
Two more short answers: these seem to be problems of both understanding and imagination. And I don't think philosophy blindness is concerned only with ethics.
Thinking about this some more, I wonder whether the question "How do you know you're not dreaming?" might be an example of seeing too much philosophy. If it's a question that really bothers you then maybe not (although that would seem like a symptom of mental illness, I think) but if it seems like something that needs to be dealt with as an intellectual but not an existential issue then that could be seeing too much philosophy.
Deletetoo many folks in philo also suffer from:
ReplyDeletehttps://rwer.wordpress.com/2015/05/04/rational-expectations-totally-incredible-bogus/
Maybe they do. This looks good: http://www.worldeconomicsassociation.org/downloads/on-the-use-and-misuse-of-theories-and-models-in-economics/
Deleteit does thanks and not being an academic press they aren't charging $150 for it, many folks (inside philo and out) working on models/rules/norms/etc should read up on 'familial' resemblances
DeleteYes, I was tempted to buy it right away.
Delete